Entre el contextualismo de Skinner y los "Perennial problems": Una propuesta para interpretar a los clasicos
Contenido principal del artículo
Este trabajo propone un enfoque metodológico, de corte hermenéutico, parainterpretar escritores políticos del pasado. El método que aquí se formula,explicitado en la última parte de este trabajo, lleva por nombre “enfoquede la doble significación de los textos clásicos”. Este hunde sus raíces enun debate acerca del valioso aporte y la profunda influencia que ha tenidola metodología para la interpretación de los textos clásicos elaborada porQuentin Skinner, como a su injustificada crítica a otras metodologías contralas cuales él levanta su propia orientación. Por lo tanto, el enfoque que aquíse propone resulta también deudor de la perspectiva de análisis a la queSkinner se enfrenta de forma radical.
Barthes, Roland (1977). Image-Music-Text.Glasgow: Fontana.
Barthes, Roland (1979). “From Work to Text”. Pp. 73-78. In: Harari, Josué (comp.), Textual Strategies. Ithaca.
Beardsley, Monroe C. (1992). “The Authority of the Text”. Pp. 24-40. In: Iseminger, Gary (comp.), Intention and Interpretation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Bellah, Robert Neelly (2008). Habits of the Heart. Individualism and Commitment in American Life. California: University of California Press.
Bloch, Marc (1982). Introducción a la historia. México: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
Bloom, Allan (1980). “The Study of Texts”. In: Political Theory and Political Education. Pp. 113-138. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Boucher, David (1984). “The Denial of Perennial Problems: The Negative Side of Quentin Skinner ́s Theory”. In: Interpretation. A Journal of Political Philosophy. May and September, Volume 12, Numbers 2 and 3.
Butterfield, Herbert (1957). George III and the Historians. London: Collins.
Cassirer, Ernst (1961). The Myth of the State. Yale: Yale University Press.
Davidson, Donald (1984). “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme”. In: Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Derrida, Jacques(1976). Of Gramatology. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Elton, Geoffrey Rudolph (1967). The Practice of History. London: Fontana Press.
Fish, Stanley (1980). Is There a Text in this Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. London: Cambridge University Press.
Foucault, Michel (1979). “What is an Author”. Pp. 141-160. In: Harari, Josué (comp.), Textual Strategies. Ithaca.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1975). Truth and Method. New York: Seabury Press.
Gilbert, Felix (1984). Machiavelli and Guicciardini. Politics and History in Sixteenth Century Florence. New York: W. W. Norton.
Graham, Keith (1981).“Illocution and Ideology”. In: Mepham, John and Ruben, David Hillel, Issues in Marxist Philosophy: Social and Political Philosophy. Sussex: The Harvester Press.
Graham, Keith (1988). “How Do Illocutionary Descriptions Explain?”. In: Tully, James (comp.), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics. London: Cambridge.
Hacker, Andrew (1954). “Capital and Carbuncles: the Great Books Reappraised”. In: American Political Science Review, 48, pp. 775-786.
Hampshire, Stuart (2000). Justice is Conflict. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Hare, Richard Mervin [1952], The Language of Morals. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hill, Christopher. (1986). People and Ideas in 17-th Century England. Massachusetts: University of Massachusetts Press.
Iser, Wolfgang (1972). “The Reading Process: A Phenomenological Approach”. In: New Literary History, 3, p. 279-299.
Koselleck, Reinhart (1993). Futuro pasado: para una semántica de los tiempos históricos. Madrid: Editorial Trotta.
Koselleck, Reinhart (2012). Historias de conceptos. Estudios sobre semántica y pragmática del lenguaje político y social. Madrid: Editorial Trotta.
Kulkarni, Mangesh (2012). “Tex and Context: Methodological Debates in the Study of Political Thought”. In: CAS Occasional Paper Series, No 5. Pune: Centre for Advanced Studies University of Pune.
Lovejoy, Arthur (1960). The Great Chain of Being. New York: Torchbook.
Lukes, Steven (1973). “On the Social Determination of Truth”. In: Horton Robin and Finnegan, Ruth (eds.), Modes of Thought: essays on thinking in Western and non-Western societies. London: Faber and Faber.
MacDonald, Graham and Pettit Philip (1980). Semantics and Social Science. London: Routledge.
MacPherson, Crawford Brough. (2010). The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Marx, Karl (1970). Tesis sobre Feuerbach: y otros escritos filosóficos. México: Ediciones Grijalbo.
Namier, Lewis Bernstein (1961). England in the Age of the American Revolution. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Pocock, John Greville Agard (2009). Political Thought and History: Essays on Theory and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pocock, John Greville Agard (2014). Politics, Language, and Time. Essays on Political Thought and History. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
Popper, Karl Raimund (1962). The Open Society and its Enemies. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Rabasa, Emilio [2011], “La escuela de Cambridge: historia del pensamiento político. Una búsqueda metodológica. En: En-claves del pensamiento, año V, Núm. 9, enero - junio.
Ricoeur, Paul (1981). “The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as a Text”. In: New Literary, 5, pp. 91-117.
Ricoeur, Paul (1981a). Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sabine, George [1949], A History of Political Theory.London: George G. Harrop & Co. Ltd.
Skinner, Quentin (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Vol. I: The Renaissance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin (2000). Machiavelli a very short introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.
Skinner, Quentin (2002a). Visions of Politics. Volume I. Regardin Method. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin (2002b). Visions of Politics. Volume III. Hobbes and Civil Science. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Strauss, Leo (1952). Persecution and the Art of Writing. Glencoe, III.: The Free Press.
Strauss, Leo (1971). “Philosophy as rigorous science and political philosophy”. Pp. 1 - 9. In: Interpretation. A journal of political philosophy. Volume 2, issue I. New York: Queens College of the City University of New York.
Strauss, Leo (1988). What is Political Philosophy?And other Studies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph (1963). The History of Political Philosophy. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Taylor, Charles (1988). “The Hermeneutics of Conflict”. In: Tully, James (comp.), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Tully, James (1988). Comp. Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Tully, James (1988). “The pen is a mighty sword: Quentin Skinner ́s analysis of politics”. In: Weber, Max (1997). Economía y sociedad: esbozo de sociología comprensiva. México: Editorial Fondo de Cultura Económica.
Weber, Max (2006). La ética protestante y el espíritu del capitalismo. Madrid: Alianza Editorial.
Weldon, Thomas Dewar [1960], The Vocabulary of Politics. Great Britain: Penguin Books.
Williams, Raymond (1983). Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wimsatt, William K. JR. and Beardsley, Monroe C.(1946). “The Intentional Fallacy”. In: The Sewanee Review, Vol. 54, No. 3 (Jul. – Sep.), pp 468-488. The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1958). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wolin, Sheldon (1960). Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought. Boston: Little, Brown.
Zuckert, Michael P. (1985). “Appropriation and Understanding in the History of Political Philosophy: On Quentin Skinner ́s Method”. In: Interpretation. A Journal of Political Philosophy. September, Volume 13, Number 3.
De acuerdo con nuestra política (Licencia Creative Commons CC BY-NC-SA 4.0) los artículos presentados y sometidos al proceso editorial en la revista Praxis Filosófica no tienen costo alguno para sus autores ni retribuciones económicas para la revista. El artículo de carácter inédito, producto de investigación o de algún proyecto que se presente a Praxis Filosófica, no podrá estar sometido a otro proceso de publicación durante el proceso que se lleve en nuestra revista.